What Is Agnosticism? (1981)
H. J. Blackham
Winds of Doctrine
As a definition of the limits of knowledge, "agnosticism" needs to be understood historically. Summarily and roughly, philosophy
at the time of Plutarch (first century A.D.) offered six positions: on the one hand, a dogmatic Idealism or Materialism: on
the other, skepticism, pragmatism, eclecticism, or fideism. The names of Plato and Democritus can be put at the head of the
dogmatic traditions: Pyrrho has lent his name to fundamental skepticism; Isocrates made immensely influential a pragmatic
view of philosophy; and Plutarch himself was the preeminent representative of a rational and ethical eclecticism. Perhaps
Tertullian, if not Saint Paul, represents the constraints of fideism after Christian faith came into contact and conflict
with Greek gnosticism.
The case for each of these positions was spelled out in verbal argument. Plato, in the Sophist (246-247), generalizes
the permanent irreconcilable conflict between Idealists and Materialists as a Battle of Gods and Giants, which transcends
the differences of the Idealist position; but he confidently assumed that they could not be insuperable, because knowledge
was not to be had on other terms. He believed in the immortality of the rational soul and the real existence of the objects
of its knowledge, which must be intelligible Ideas or Forms, independent of sense perceptions. Protagoras had already sounded
the agnostic note, it may be said, with his "of all things the measure is Man," and explicitly: "As to the gods, I have no
means of knowing either that they exist or that they do not exist." But it is Isocrates who opposed the whole bent of academic
philosophy in his development of the rationalizing Enlightenment of the sophists, a rationalism critical of and ready to ridicule
"pure reason," the "phronesis" or idea of wisdom, which was the nuclear element in the development of Plato's though. This
attainable intuitional knowledge was for Plato not only a view of all time and all existence sub specie aeternitatis
but also the indispensable source of the right ordering of personal life and public affairs. Isocrates argued that no such
knowledge was attainable that would suffice for all occasions and all purposes. Instead, he maintained, cultivation of the
art of discourse, relevant to the whole life of civilized man and dealing with great causes and large ideas, was the best
preparation for the most complete competence attainable. There was no institution devised by man that the power of speech
had not helped to establish (Antidosis). The art of rhetoric and the art of thought were the same. The ability to deliberate
and decide was the most versatile and useful of all abilities. This was to recommend and to teach method instead of doctrine,
an open approach which, if it did not turn opinions into doctrines with the claim of knowledge, in the manner of the schools,
provided a foundation for higher education and intellectual culture, a literary humanism occupied with large human affairs
and concerns and addressed concretely to manifest problems with all the seriousness, but not necessarily with the detachment
and never with the dryness, of the philosophic spirit. Isocrates was the most illustrious teacher of his time and made his
school "the image of Athens." The pupils of Athens, as he said, became "the teachers of the rest of the word" (Panegyricus).
However, the arguments of a discourse were not tautologies that could be ended with a Euclidean flourish: Q.E.D. The wits
exercised in such performances were capable of producing a plausible argument on the other side that might be made to seem
not less persuasive. Indeed, Protagoras had laid down that there are two sides to every question and an opposing argument
to any proposed, and he taught how to attack and refute any proposition. Since he also first introduced the Socratic method
of dialogue and drew attention to distinction of tense and mood and to divisions of discourse, he pioneered development of
the technical resources of argument, as well as exploiting for profit the tricks of the trade. Thus eristic theory and techniques,
and what was sometimes called "methodics," became central to philosophy; and a high proportion of a philosopher's output was
in this category, including even collections of refutative arguments, solutions of controversial questions, materials for
argument, unscientific proofs, and the like. Diogenes Laertius listed many such works among the writings of Aristotle and
Aristotle's pupil and successor, Theophrastus. Aristotle himself distinguished between methods for attaining knowledge, principally
philosophical analysis, and methods of arguing in favor of the probable, principally dialectic.
With all this development of technical resources and refinements in argument in classical philosophy, there was no knockout
device to determine a definitive outcome. On the scientific side, there were systematic collections of observations in the
search for causes, particularly in Aristotle's innumerable notebooks. But it is not too much to say that the manipulation
of arguments and the collection of evidence (save of the kind needed in legal prosecution or defense) remained different disciplines
and separate interests in classical philosophy.
The First Turning-Point
In the second half of the sixteenth century, Montaigne read himself into the classical inheritance for a different purpose
-- on a course of free inquiry. He discovered the interminable inconclusiveness of argument of verbal philosophy, and he ended
with the ultimate doubt: Que sais-je? Blown, like Augustine, by the winds of doctrine, he could not feel safe in any
of the positions; even skepticism was too unjustifiably conclusive. Pascal, reporting to his confessor on his reading, told
him that he most respected Epictetus and Montaigne and, in summarizing their opinions for him, he said a discourse was to
take it as it appeared and refrain from any examination, which would at once reveal difficulties and raise doubts. This is
the professional routine of the philosopher and shows how brittle is the most careful discourse and how treacherous verbal
answers are to free inquiry.
A little later, Francis Bacon, who, like Montaigne, was painfully aware that the whole legacy of classical philosophy was
a discouragement to learning, set himself the task of reviving hope with a vision of the future inspired by the early successes
of empirical methods of testing hypotheses. The loose, but reasonable, appeal to experience had to be refined as an appeal
to a specifically devised experience constructed to test a particular theory. Within its limits, this was a decisive way of
settling theoretical disputes. Novum Organum (1620) spelled out the new method of learning, which was to displace the
literary humanism of Isocrates as the foundation of a positivist culture, obtaining knowledge piecemeal and cooperatively,
provisional, corrigible, progressive, to be applied to "the relief of man's estate." Bacon, godfather of the Royal Society
and acknowledged master of the philosophes in Diderot's Encyclopédie, left the winds of doctrine to blow where
they listed and gave his attention to cultivation of the soil. In particular, his organum was a replacement of the magisterial
Metaphysics of Aristotle and made way for the atomic model of Democritus. All the same, he did not set aside or put in question
the assumption of theism. On the contrary, he counted on the new learning to fortify belief:
God
never wrought miracle to convince atheism, because His ordinary works convince it. It is true that a little philosophy inclineth
man's mind to atheism; but depth in philosophy bringeth men's minds about to religion: for while the mind of man looketh upon
second causes scattered, it may sometimes rest in them, and go no farther; but when it beholdeth the chain of them confederate
and linked together, it must needs fly to Providence and Deity. Nay, even that school which is most accused of atheism doth
most demonstrate religion. For it is a thousand times more credible, that four mutable elements, and one immutable fifth essence
duly and eternally placed, need no God; than that an army of infinite small portions, or seeds unplaced, should have produced
this order and beauty without a divine Marshall. ["Of Atheism"]
Thus the clear-sighted Bacon, looking backward and forward and setting the minds of his contemporaries on the bright prospects
opening up for empirical investigation and the technological manipulation of nature, had not in his own mind set science free
from metaphysical assumptions and interests.
God on Trial
During this "century of genius," which produced the first spectacular fruits of modern science, those working in the fields
of investigation did, like Bacon, assume that they were piecing together the divine design, enabled, as Kepler said, to "think
the thoughts of God." Studying together, fraternally, the works of God, they were more blessed than students of the Word of
God, who had taxed each other with heresy and soaked in blood the centuries beginning anno Domini. Science was another road
to God, a second, less disputable revelation. Professional scientists, led by Newton, were amateur theologians. Since there
was an order in nature that was being unraveled, it was only reasonable to assume, with Bacon, that it was the work of a rational,
purposive intelligence that linked and sustained the whole. The onus was on anyone who thought otherwise to face the odds
and justify their own irrationality. John Locke, who enthusiastically welcomed the new regime of empirical investigation and
sought to provide its theoretical credentials, and who downgraded philosophers from architects of knowledge to under-laborers
on the site of building operations, caring for the tools and preparing the ground, also was witness for the reasonableness
of religious belief and excluded atheists from his republic of toleration -- on the ground that they were not bound by an
oath. God was necessary politically as well as intellectually.
This general assumption that the new learning of science would not only establish positive knowledge but also bring its
proofs to the basic beliefs that had been justified by unscientific proofs lasted till the end of the eighteenth century.
It has been said that during this period "God was on trial."
The Second Turning-Point
The critical philosophy of David Hume, reinforced later by Kant (who said that Hume has awakened us from "dogmatic slumbers"),
put in question the status and character of positive knowledge. He pointed out that it was simply knowledge of regular sequences
and coexistences as presented to our observation of phenomena and did not carry or imply knowledge of causes, powers, natures,
essences, or purposes. This began the disassociation of science from metaphysics, surrendering any claim on its behalf to
answer general questions. With the steady progress of the sciences and the analytical attention of philosophers to what scientists
were doing, it became abundantly clear that science was capable of dealing only with questions arising in the course of a
line of research that were formulated in a way to provide answers that could be tested. Loose questions, general questions,
first and last questions, the traditional metaphysical questions, were not a kind with which science was, or would ever be,
competent to deal. During the period of trial science not only had not proved the existence of God, it had not even been able
to do anything to reinforce the assumption. Laplace declared that he had no need of that hypothesis, and of course he had
none. His statement was really about the irrelevance of that hypothesis to scientific business, not about its truth claim.
Thus, to look back at Bacon's statement in "Of Atheism," God's ordinary works as studied in the sciences did not "convince
atheism," since they were preoccupied with "second causes scattered" and went no farther. He had begged the question when
he went farther to say that Providence and Deity were necessary to link them in a chain, a rational order. Auguste Comte,
too, anticipated the issue when he announced at the end of his Cours philosophique in 1851 that the servants of Humanity,
theorists and practical persons, had irrevocably displaced the slaves of God and taken the management of earthly affairs into
their own hands, to construct at last the true providence: moral, intellectual, and material. Comte said he was not an atheist
because that was to take theology seriously, whereas the ages of theology and metaphysics were past and done with, succeeded
by the positive sciences. On the side counter to Bacon in this respect, Comte claimed too much for the competence of science.
But the overweening claims of theology were being checked, the onus on the unbeliever to justify his perverse irrationality
reversed.
Logically, there was a return to the position of Protagoras after the lapse of more than two millennia. Science could not
cope with metaphysical questions. They belonged as before to the about, the about of interminable inconclusive argument. Had
science, then, made no difference? If metaphysical theories were irrelevant to the sciences, were scientific findings equally
irrelevant to metaphysical theories? Even abstract arguments rely on evidence. The answer can be given in two main installments.
(1) The physical sciences in their earlier stages seemed to offer models of harmony and design, eminently attributable
to a supreme intelligence. Biological studies were sooner to encounter doubts and difficulties for a teleological view. When
the evidence produced by Darwin, and his theories, showed the possibility of an order in nature that was not purposive, a
turning point was reached. The ambiguity of "reason" in the interpretation of nature became apparent. There were reasons for
what had happened, but not necessarily any reason. The absurdity of unbelief in a supreme reason (with or without capitals)
was exposed as an unwarranted assumption. It was at this point that T.H. Huxley, Darwin's advocate, invented the word "agnosticism"
(1869) to reinstate the position of Protagoras. The onus was shifted from the shoulders of the unbeliever to justify his perversity,
to the shoulders of the believer to justify his belief, to show why he should be taken seriously.
(2) More indirectly, and on all fronts, scientific evidence has demolished the world in which traditional theological beliefs
originated and developed. To bring them out of their context, to demythologize and reinterpret them is a delicate, maybe gratuitous,
task for modern theologians; so their survival is more remarkable than impressive. Argument will go on, as always, and becomes
ever more refined or sophisticated; and when religious beliefs are concerned, argument is not the whole matter and, for many,
not the main matter. Intellectually, however, a disregard for religious beliefs does not have to be justified, as once it
had, with its back to the wall. The boot is on the other foot. Historically, "agnosticism" does not merely mean a suspension
of judgment. Rather, it means intellectual justification for a disregard of theology.
[H.J. Blackham is former president of the British Humanist Association and the author of many books on humanism and
philosophy.]
|